Detailed guides to painful problems, treatments & more

Can the mind create pain? (Member Post)

 •  • by Paul Ingraham
Get posts in your inbox:
Weekly nuggets of pain science news and insight, usually 100-300 words, with the occasional longer post. The blog is the “director’s commentary” on the core content of PainScience.com: a library of major articles and books about common painful problems and popular treatments. See the blog archives or updates for the whole site.

PainSci Member Login

Submit your email to unlock this audio content (and any other stuff for members). If you can’t remember or access your registration email, please contact me. ~ Paul Ingraham, PainSci Publisher

Privacy & Security of this form This login is private and secure: the information you submit is encrypted, used only to search for matching accounts, and then discarded.

How do you know if your pain is psychosomatic? Can our minds create pain, out of nothing? Can we have pain for psychological reasons alone? Does such pure psychosomatic pain exist — pain with no injury at all, no issue in the tissue, no noxious stimuli of any kind?

Can we “hallucinate” pain?

Short answer: probably not, as far as I’ve been able to determine. But I do not know, and I am not done trying. The mind can harm us in ways that lead to pain in time, and it might be able to amplify pain, but so far I have be unable to find any clear evidence that the mind can generate pain from nothing, with no injury or pathology. And there seem to be many reasons to suspect that it either isn’t possible at all, or it’s rather rare and associated with relatively glaring mental illness.

The head of a man composed of writhing nude figures. Oil painting by F. Balbi.

Please err on the side of assuming pain is never psychosomatic

If it exists at all, pure all-in-your-head chronic pain is probably quite rare. Unexplained chronic pain is often inappropriately, prematurely chalked up to psychology, and often for terrible reasons (e.g. sexism), with terrible outcomes. “Patients often find themselves trapped in a zone between the worlds of medicine and psychiatry, with neither community taking full responsibility.” (O’Sullivan) In a great many cases, there is a biological cause that simply hasn’t been diagnosed yet.

In other words, most pain patients need better diagnosis, not fixes for a non-existent psychological issue. So we should avoid a diagnosis of psychosomatic pain like the plague. It should be one of the last things we think about, if we ever do.

But it’s really important in principle — and interesting — to know if it’s possible for the mind to generate pain out of nothing.

The long answer? That’s behind the wall of payment

This is a member’s only post, and … it’s a sloppy one! It’s a half-baked draft! Great sales pitch, eh?

I have usually worked my tail off to make most member posts very “premium” — my best work, high polish, cream of the crop. But I also always meant to share more sneak previews of works-in-progress, invite members to look behind the curtain, see content in development, and even contribute to that development. I am going to get useful replies to this post. You, dear reader, are going to supply examples and analogies I haven’t thought of yet, studies I haven’t seen, and arguments I haven’t considered. Why don’t you hit me with your best shot, hit me with your best shot, fire away?

But even half-baked, this post is another couple thousand words, and it’s not really all that sloppy. I’m not exactly a beginner with this topic. 😜

 MEMBERS-ONLY AREA

PainSci Member Login

Submit your email to unlock member content. If you can’t remember or access your registration email, please contact me. ~ Paul Ingraham, PainSci Publisher

Privacy & Security of this form This login is private and secure: the information you submit is encrypted, used only to search for matching accounts, and then discarded.

Can’t stop believin': the psychosomatic paradox

Amazingly, no one actually knows for sure if psychogenic pain is a genuine phenomenon. Certainly no one wants to believe that their own chronic pain is psychogenic. An “all in your head” diagnosis — or obnoxious subtext — has become a cliché of medical gaslighting.

Ironically, despite that hated phrase, almost everyone does believe that it is possible for pain to be all in your head. The whole idea of mindbody medicine is smash cultural hit. This is a peculiar paradox!

So what is it? Do we believe or don’t we? Can pain be “all” in our own heads… or just other people’s heads? And if we don’t think pain can be psychosomatic at all, then what’s with all the bestselling self-help books about mindbody medicine, the endless torrent of fear-mongering rhetoric about the evils of stress?

It’s bizarre how obsessed we are with a theory of health that every chronic pain patient also seems to loathe.

The scope of this article

But this is about evidence and arguments for existence of pure psychogenic pain, occurring the perfect absence of any pathology or trauma of any kind. I will only consider pain amplification and other kinds of psychosomatic illness only insofar as they inform this central question.

The psychosomatic pain glossary

  • Sensation — The conversion of a physical stimuli into nerve impulses and then some kind of conscious awareness of that stimulus.
  • Nociception — The conversion of noxious stimuli into nerve impulses, which may or may not lead to pain.
  • Sensitization — Increased nociception relative to stimulus.
  • Perception — The organization, interpretation, and conscious experience of sensations.
  • Amplification — Pain that is out of proportion to a noxious stimulus due to perception. This is distinct from “amplified pain syndrome.”1
  • Suffering — A negative emotional experience.

Proving psychogenic pain requires proving a negative

There is no reasonably direct evidence of pure psychogenic pain as far as I know. All we seem to have is speculative arguments, mostly based on inference and extrapolation from other phenomena. “If x is possible, then maybe psychosomatic pain is also possible…”

To be sure that pain is psychosomatic, we must also be sure that it has no undiagnosed biological cause. But we can only ever be “quite” sure of that, at best — and we are rarely at our best in this way. Most professionals are ignorant of the scope of the possibilities, and tend to underestimate them.2

There are countless hard-to-diagnose causes of pain, and much about the physiology of pain remains mysterious. Some chronic painful conditions rarely have known causes. For instance, a staggering percentage of back pain is “non-specific,” or not attributable to any specific cause, there’s been a running battle for decades now over how many of those cases have a biological cause or trigger that simply can’t be easily identified, versus a psychogenic cause. Is it 60-40? 30-70? We can never really know.

Separating psychosomatic pain from suffering and alarm

And there are other basic limits on our ability to know if the mind can create pain. It’s nearly impossible to tease apart pain and suffering, for instance. Pain is entirely subjective — it is what people say it is. But the intensity of pain that people report can be a product of either:

  1. a more intense sensation
  2. and/or its emotional significance.

Does someone say that a pain is a 6 out of 10 on the pain scale because the sensation is that strong? Or because they are freaked out? Or both? Probably both, but in what proportion? It’s different for every person and every problem, and there is never any way to know.

The puzzle of pain’s subjectivity: how can we know if pain is “too loud”?

Again, pain is subjective, and cannot be “wrong.” No one can tell anyone they aren’t in pain, or “shouldn’t” be. Technically, we cannot ever know that any one example of pain is “too loud,” because there is never a knowably “right” (objective) amount of pain for any situation, or even a fully knowable situation (there could always be a sneaky cause we cannot detect). This puzzle cannot be solved any more than we can ever really know if someone is seeing reds that are “too red.” The pure subjectivity of pain places an absolute limit on our ability to judge whether it is “amplified.”3

But don’t be fooled: that is a technical limitation we have ways of working around. It’s no different than what psychiatry has always had to grapple with: pathologies that obviously exist, and yet have only subjective symptoms. How do we diagnose those? How can we know that a patient’s experience is “wrong”? By how much it is at odds with reality as we understand it from other people, and by how much distress and trouble it causes. If someone is extremely tormented by perceptions of things that no one else can perceive at all, we call that mental illness, and no one worries too much about the fact that we can’t actually prove that it is — not at the extremes anyway. Life is all about these good-enough guesses.

Consider the example of electrosensitivity, a clear example of a painful mental illness: people who report great pain and suffering caused by something that cannot plausibly harm them. In any one case, we cannot technically prove that their pain is wrong. And yet we can have very high confidence that the electrosensitives cannot all be right: most of them must be reporting pain that has no biological cause.

Psychosomatic pain versus pain-without-nociception

Some readers will notice that question of the existence of psychosomatic pain is just another version of the debate about whether we can have “pain without nociception” — a staple of dorky shop talk on social media for the last few years.

The concepts do overlap greatly, but there is one key difference: “psychosomatic” strongly implies mental illness, a pattern of lasting and consequential symptoms. Examples of pain-without-nociception are often more like “brain farts” — little isolated glitches in perception, more like being fooled by an optical illusion than a “hallucination” of pain.

Arguments for pain without nociception

In the absence of good evidence that pain can exist without nociception, there are various arguments, suggestive examples, and lines of indirect evidence instead. They are all interesting in their own right, but none of seem to be up to the task. They all have issues. I’ll summarize them here, and elaborate on some of them below.

  • Psychological stress and anxiety are implicated as major factors in almost every imaginable kind of health problem, and the weight of those example is so great that it seems like a no-brainer that stress and anxiety must be able to cause pain as well. However, it’s clear the there’s usually or always an intermediate causal mechanism, such as muscle tension or an ulcer. In other words, we might hurt because stress and anxiety cause or aggravate a painful illness.
  • Boot-nail-guy is the best example of these kinds of examples: a case study of a fellow who experienced great pain because he thought a nail had gone through his foot, but in fact it had gone through his toes. But we simply don’t know enough about exactly what happened. I’ve written in detail about Boot Nail Guy.
  • Phantom limb pain seems like an example of pain that exists entirely in the mind, since the hurting tissue no longer exists. Except that it does: it’s the severed nerve endings in the stump that generate the nociception, and the brain just can’t work out where the signal is coming from. It’s clearly just an example of misperception of the location of the arm, and not pain without any nociception at all.4
  • Nocebo is the well-documented phenomenon of fear-powered symptoms that seems to show that psychosomatic pain is possible. It may be one of the best arguments for psychosomatic pain, but it’s also not quite the slam dunk it looks like. More below.
  • The phenomenon of sensitization can be used to make the case that pain can be generated from nothing, especially the phenomenon like allodynia — pain from non-noxious stimuli. However, sensitization involves sensory amplification — a stronger signal, not a stronger perception.
  • Central post-stroke pain is a promising candidate for pain that unambiguously comes from a “bad brain,” and definitely not peripheral nociception. So it partially and vividly meets some of the criteria for psychosomatic pain, and it can be considered “hallucinatory.” But that’s the brain, not the mind: pain that arises from brain damage (central neuropathy), and not psychology. So … still not “psychosomatic.”5
  • The functional neurological disorders — people who suffer blindness, paralysis, or seizures — are one of the most vivid demonstrations of the power of the mind, but it’s also not a direct analogy: they don’t involve novel perceptions.
  • Hallucination happens, and this has led some people to suggest that if you can perceive other things without stimulus, you can probably hallucinate pain too. This is quite compelling on its face, but the deal-breaker is that other kinds of hallucination always have a biological cause: either pathology or drugs. People perceive things that aren’t there when their brain is impaired or altered… not because of their psychology.
  • Electromagnetic sensitivity is a real illness in which people report pain in response to something that cannot actually harm them, which might mean that their pain is psychosomatic. However, it might also mean that they all just have an undiagnosed pathology (e.g. fibromyalgia), and the EMS thing is just a hypothesis they’ve embraced to explain it. Once that hypothesis is embraced, the obsessiveness and paranoia about EMF very naturally follows — but it gets them labelled as mentally ill.

There’s no chance this list is complete yet, and this is the most obvious way in which this is a work-in-progress. I await your can’t-believe-you-didn’t-mention emails!

Is nocebo the example we’re looking for?

Placebo is “relief from belief,” and nocebo is the opposite: “grief from belief.” Just as placebo is widely believed tobe a fascinating example of the power of the mind over the body, so too is nocebo thought of as a vivid example of a psychosomatic phenomenon. If nocebo is a thing (and that is widely accepted), then psychosomatic pain is probably a thing.

Unfortunately, it’s not a clean win. It’s not that nocebo doesn’t exist, but it’s not what seems like. Some complications:

  1. The Legend of Placebo is that it is “powerful,”6 but it probably isn’t powerful — not in the psychosomatic sense, anyway. “Expectation effects” appear to be limited to perception and are quite modest.7 Much of what is called placebo is not an expectation effect at all, but merely the appearance of it in a research context.8
  2. Just because placebo might be able to reduce the perception of existing pain doesn’t mean that nocebo can generate the perception of pain from nothing. Even if nocebo is a legitimate phenomenon, it might be limited to amplification of existing nociception, as opposed to causing the perception of pain in the absence of nociception.
  3. Nocebo may cause an increase in alarm and drama about pain, rather than pain itself.

There are impressive examples of placebo that are hard to dismiss. My favourite is “beet guy,” a story in the excellent book Pain: The science and culture of why we hurt, about a man who was rescued from agony by learning that his bright red poop was caused not by internal bleeding but… beets!9 So where did all the “agony” come from? Certainly not the beets! Is this an open-and-shut case? No, because it’s so hard to distinguish pain from panic. And because he might have actually had simultaneous indigestion.

Indirectly psychogenic pain — from mind to [insert something] to pain

Tension headache is a common, minor example of how mental state can directly drive pain with no clear intermediate mechanism … and this kind of pain is often rounded up to “psychosomatic.” But there probably is a mechanism for all headaches, it’s just murky, and we don’t even know if it’s “tension.” This is likely the case for many painful conditions.

Holding your hand over a candle isn’t an example of psychogenic pain — but why not? It was your foolish mind’s idea! But no one in their right mind would say that it was your mind that cause the pain. It was the candle, obviously!

But what if you replace “candle” with “cramp”? What if your mind causes a painful muscle tension or spasm? This is one hypothetical mechanism for some kinds of pain (and just as scientifically mysterious and uncertain).10 In this case, the links between “mind” and “pain” are more unconscious and subtle. You might have no awareness of the intermediate muscle causal between your mind and your pain, which makes it seem a lot more like mind-powered pain.

Such ideas might partly explain how the mind can be involved in causing pain without actually generating it from scratch, and may also help to convince people that psychogenic pain is a legit phenomenon. But they are not examples of pure psychogenic pain — a biological mechanism is still needed. The problem may have begun with a thought and ended with a perception, but the flesh still got involved in the middle, even if you couldn’t tell.

If we can paralyze ourselves, we can probably make ourselves hurt

Functional neurological disorders definitely exist — and they seem closely related to psychosomatic pain.

The FNDs, formerly known as “conversion” disorders, make it abundantly clear that the mind does have some crazy powers. We can experience seizures, paralysis, blindness, and other neurological symptoms in the absence of neurological disease.1112 Strange but true!

The FNDs that we know do not generally involve wonky perception, but wonky function — it’s right in the name. Nevertheless, if we can paralyze ourselves with our minds, it does seems like we might be capable of invent pain too. In fact, some chronic pain might actually be one of the members of the FND family, just really difficult to confirm, because pain can have so many other causes. In contrast, seizures, paralysis, and blindness have relatively short lists of possible causes to eliminate, leaving only the power of the mind to explain the problem. And so, once again, no one really knows.

Notably "an FND that causes only pain" is actually indistinguishable from psychosomatic pain — different labels for the same concept.

However, inference from the known types of FNDs might be a compelling clue that pure psychosomatic pain is possible.

And that’s as far as I am going to get with this topic today. 🙂 I am well aware of at least a dozen more sub-topics I didn’t tackle, and I could keep chipping away at them for weeks before sharing this… but I’d rather share it now. I am really looking forward to getting your comments, suggestions, and criticisms. The final product will be much better for it.

Notes

  1. The label "Amplified Pain Syndrome" refers mainly to a controversial diagnosis of psychosomatic pain in children. In this article, I’ve used "amplification" in a more general sense, and one that isn't widely used in the scientific literature. The concept is common, but it has no widely accepted formal term that I know of.
  2. My favourite personal anecdote about this is the time I consulted a neurologist because I was having "thunderclap headaches." I had just read a scientific paper about well *over one hundred* distinct pathological types of thunderclap headaches. But because I didn't have a brain bleed, my neurologist declared authoritatively that I was fine, that there were only a couple of other causes of thunderclap headache and they weren't dangerous. He was egregiously wrong … and I don’t actually think he was a bad doctor.
  3. Weisman A, Quintner J, Masharawi Y. Amplified Pain Syndrome-An Insupportable Assumption. JAMA Pediatr. 2021 Mar. PubMed 33683311 ❐
  4. Ilfeld BM, Khatibi B, Maheshwari K, et al. Ambulatory continuous peripheral nerve blocks to treat postamputation phantom limb pain: a multicenter, randomized, quadruple-masked, placebo-controlled clinical trial. Pain. 2021 03;162(3):938–955. PubMed 33021563 ❐ PainSci Bibliography 51431 ❐
  5. Treister AK, Hatch MN, Cramer SC, Chang EY. Demystifying Poststroke Pain: From Etiology to Treatment. PM R. 2017 Jan;9(1):63–75. PubMed 27317916 ❐ PainSci Bibliography 51204 ❐
  6. Beecher HK. The powerful placebo. J Am Med Assoc. 1955 Dec;159(17):1602–6. PubMed 13271123 ❐

    This is the 1955 paper that launched the Legend of Placebo. Dr. Henry Beecher reported that 35% of 1000 patients were “satisfactorily” treated with a placebo alone. His conclusion catapulted placebo to lasting fame… and wasn't really questioned for a long time.

    Kienle and Kiene published a strong criticism of Beecher's findings in 1996, but no one took much notice. Much more prominently, Hróbjartsson and Gøtzsche reported in 2001 in the New England Journal of Medicine that they “found little evidence in general that placebos had powerful clinical effects” and concluded that there is “no justification for the use of placebos” outside clinical trials.

    The topic has been hotly debated ever since, but few experts still believe that placebo is “powerful.”

    For much more about Beecher and how this all started, see The Legend of the Wartime Placebo

  7. Hróbjartsson A, Gøtzsche PC. Is the placebo powerless? Update of a systematic review with 52 new randomized trials comparing placebo with no treatment. J Intern Med. 2004 Aug;256(2):91–100. PubMed 15257721 ❐

    This paper was the first widely discussed challenge to the claim that placebo is “powerful” (starting with the first version in 2001, see Hróbjartsson, which following a more obscure paper by Kienle in 1997). Hróbjartsson and Gøtzsche “found little evidence in general that placebos had powerful clinical effects” and concluded that there is “no justification for the use of placebos” outside clinical trials. The topic has been hotly debated ever since, but few experts still believe that placebo is “powerful.”

  8. ScienceBasedMedicine.org [Internet]. Brissonnet J. Placebo, Are You There?; 2015 Mar 12 [cited 22 May 26]. PainSci Bibliography 54158 ❐
  9. Jackson M. Pain: The science and culture of why we hurt. Trade paperback ed. Random House; 2003.
  10. Cramps and twitches are the tip of the iceberg — there are many major types of unwanted muscle contractions. There are also many myths about them: dehydration doesn’t cause cramps, “stiffness” isn’t caused by “tight” muscles, and “back spasm” is just a way of saying how back pain feels, not how it works. While many common aches and pains feel crampy, no one knows if there is any such thing as a contraction that can cause pain without being otherwise seen or felt — but it is possible. See Cramps, Spasms, Tremors & Twitches: The biology and treatment of unwanted muscle contractions.
  11. Espay AJ, Aybek S, Carson A, et al. Current Concepts in Diagnosis and Treatment of Functional Neurological Disorders. JAMA Neurol. 2018 09;75(9):1132–1141. PubMed 29868890 ❐
  12. O’Sullivan S. It's All in Your Head: True Stories of Imaginary Illness. Chatto & Windus; 2015.

    This book consists mainly of well-told stories of severe psychosomatic illness and functional neurological disorders (neurological symptoms without diagnosable disease). The key take-away is that psychologically powered illness is common and can be amazingly severe. Although Dr. O’Sullivan is clearly concerned about the risk of incorrect diagnosis, and she is cautious and compassionate enough that I think she mostly gets it right (with the notable exception of the chronic fatigue chapter). It’s well-written and fascinating and has plenty to offer. I do wish there were citations.

↑ MEMBERS-ONLY AREA ↑